-->
The
impressive model of art history bequeathed by the confluence of
Wölfflin and the Viennese may be regarded as a theory of the middle
range. As such, the brilliance of the total achievement was
extraordinary. Yet most adherents to this model offered neither a
detailed analysis of individual works nor a broad contextualization
of art in relation to other branches of human endeavor. Voices were
raised, then, asking that the "scale" of art history be
extended in either direction. Some favored a phenomenological
approach that would savor intensely the particulars of individual
works--what might be provisionally termed micro-art history--while
others strove to lay the foundations of a generalist methodology that
would securely place art works in a broad context--macro-art history.
The
particularism of the first trend had its roots in the early
nineteenth century, when the humanities sought to define their own
sphere, protecting it from incursions from the natural sciences with
their reliance on general laws. In Jerusalem
(1818) William Blake opined that "[h]e who would do good to
another must do it in Minute Particulars." Towards the end of
the nineteenth century the German philosopher Wilhelm Windelband
(1848-1915) defined the method of the humanities as idiographic,
concerned with specifics, as against the nomothetic method of the
sciences, with their striving to formulate general laws.
Art
scholars, Windelband's contemporaries, tended to approach their
idiographic task through the subdiscipline of connoisseurship.
Connoisseurship: Forerunners.
Connoisseurship
is closely linked with the theories of Giovanni Morelli in the
latter part of the nineteenth century--and rightly so. Yet the
method did not spring forth without any preparation, for the the method's roots stem from the Baroque period. In his Considerazioni
sulla pittura
(ca. 1620) the Roman amateur Giulio Mancini held that sophisticated
appreciators of painting must address three types of
knowledge: quality, authorship or authenticity, and originality.i
Although Mancini's treatise was for a long time available only in
manuscript, the ideas trickled out to leading Italian and French
writers. Of these the most influential was Roger de Piles
(1635-1709), who attached an essay on the matter to his Abrégé
de la vie des peintres
(1699).ii
It was
from these sources, and from the philosophy of John Locke, that
Jonathan Richardson Senior (1665-1745), a portrait painter and
collector, formed the methodology of his ambitious Two
Discourses
(1719). As Carol Gibson-Wood observes "Richardson sought to
promote connoisseurship as a branch of knowledge, a 'science' in the
eighteenth-century sense of the word. As such it could be mastered
by anyone capable of thinking clearly and reasoning correctly, but
demanded a rational, empirical method of procedure."iii
In contrast to Morelli's later method, which focused on tell-tale
individual traits, Richardson believed that one should judge quality
and authorship by a careful consideration of the effect conveyed by
the work as a whole. He based his own observations on his huge
private collection of drawings, which he would compare with paintings
wherever possible. Because of his belief that connoisseurship was a
rational procedure, accessible to anyone who would take the
trouble, his views went against the elitist sense--one deeply
cherished by the art-loving aristocracy--that this sensibility was a special gift
accorded only to a few individuals. For this reason the Richardson approach met little success in his day, only to recur in a
different form in the late-nineteenth-century notion of a "science
of art" (Kunstwissenschaft).
Although
the idea is implicit in his work, Richardson did not use the word
"connoisseurship" itself--as distinct from "connoisseur,"
which he frequently employed. The abstract noun connoisseurship did
not come into common use in English until the middle of the
eighteenth century, the sense being conveyed previously by the French
import connoissance.
The implication is that the observer attains an awareness of variations among works of art over a period of time.
The imported term relied on a French (and German) distinction
between two verbs for knowledge: connaître
and savoir
(or kennen
and wissen).
The distinction is not so easily expressed in English, though it can
be understood. Connaître suggests intuitive capacities (which some observers today locate on the right side of the brain),
while savoir implies "hard knowledge" (on the left side of the
brain).
Connoisseurship
ultimately stems from the collecting trend.iv
The working artist is usually too busy, or too partial in his or her
judgments to pore over the works of others, trying to identify their
particular excellences. But the leisured collector may do
so. Some of the writers on art previously discussed, including
Malvasia and Rumohr, were amateurs
of this type. This kind of appreciation paralleled that of
the enthusiast for literature, who excelled in spotting particular
effects in the Greek and Latin classics, though less commonly in modern
works. Sometimes this practice reached an extreme of critical
finickiness, as in the fictional Signor Pococurante satirized in
Voltaire's Candide
(1759), who found fault even with Homer, Vergil, and Milton.
Some owners of very elaborate collections hired experts to organize their art collections for them; the archetype here is the industrious Filippo Baldinucci (1624-1696), a full-time art expert for the Medici family in Florence. Moreover, the emergence of the art trade in seventeenth-century Holland encouraged comparison of various works in order to appraise them and weed out forgeries. The dealer also needed to cultivate a sales patter, which sometimes took the form of alerting the the potential purchaser to various particular "beauties" found in the object on sale.
Some owners of very elaborate collections hired experts to organize their art collections for them; the archetype here is the industrious Filippo Baldinucci (1624-1696), a full-time art expert for the Medici family in Florence. Moreover, the emergence of the art trade in seventeenth-century Holland encouraged comparison of various works in order to appraise them and weed out forgeries. The dealer also needed to cultivate a sales patter, which sometimes took the form of alerting the the potential purchaser to various particular "beauties" found in the object on sale.
Towards
the end of the nineteenth century these several trends converged in a
new type of expert, the connoisseur. Such individuals claimed to have raised
critical appreciation to a scientific level. As we have seen,
the methods used by these experts were largely inherited ones. Yet
the social context was different, for the nineteenth century saw a
proliferation of public museums and galleries. Some of these
resulted from the opening of former princely collections to anyone
willing to pay a small admission fee. Others, like the national
galleries in London and Berlin, had to start from scratch. The new
museums required worthy objects to exhibit, and this appetite
stimulated the art market. As it happened, the French Revolution and
the Napoleonic period had disrupted many institutions, especially
ecclesiastical ones, which had enjoyed the custody of works by famous
artists. In many instances works had been alienated from their
original owners during the Revolutionary period and had entered the
art market. In other cases, demoralized or impoverished owners were compelled to part with their treasures at prices that the acquirers,
generally well-healed northern Europeans, found eminently affordable.
In this
ebullient art market, the connoisseur found a role as the guarantor
of the attribution of the work: he certified that a work claimed as a
Lotto was a Lotto and a Reni was a Reni, and so forth. Since
connoisseurs would usually receive a commission for such
attestations, so that venal temptations to upgrade works, by claiming that,
say, a Timoteo Viti was actually a Raphael were ever present. Of course high-level connoisseurs claimed the status of Caesar's wife: they were incapable of such transgressions. But were they? Even today it is hard to be sure in some cases.
In addition to offering expertise concerning works on the art market (sometimes lodged, interestingly enough, in their own collections), connoisseurs felt the call to evaluate the works newly displayed in the major public collections. In a good many instances they found that the existing attributions were false, or at least overoptimistic, since works by pupils or even outright forgeries passed as originals by great masters. Here too, however, commercial considerations obtruded. Deattributing a "Luini," let us say, might have adverse affects on related works still in private hands. This erosion of status would effect not only "Luinis" but also Luinis, genuine articles nonetheless tainted by association with the suspect work. In this way the task of the connoisseur intersected with commerce. Before purchasing, customers often demanded a written certificate by a recognized authority, whose income depended on a steady flow of such requests. Yet if widespread venality were suspected, consumer confidence would disappear and the whole edifice would come crashing down. From all this one should not assume that inflation of reputations was widespread; it was simply a continuing undercurrent. The proof that, on the whole, the connoisseurs did not accede to this temptation is found in this fact: globally speaking, the canon of works attributed to many great masters shrank, as new methods of evaluation were stringently applied.
In addition to offering expertise concerning works on the art market (sometimes lodged, interestingly enough, in their own collections), connoisseurs felt the call to evaluate the works newly displayed in the major public collections. In a good many instances they found that the existing attributions were false, or at least overoptimistic, since works by pupils or even outright forgeries passed as originals by great masters. Here too, however, commercial considerations obtruded. Deattributing a "Luini," let us say, might have adverse affects on related works still in private hands. This erosion of status would effect not only "Luinis" but also Luinis, genuine articles nonetheless tainted by association with the suspect work. In this way the task of the connoisseur intersected with commerce. Before purchasing, customers often demanded a written certificate by a recognized authority, whose income depended on a steady flow of such requests. Yet if widespread venality were suspected, consumer confidence would disappear and the whole edifice would come crashing down. From all this one should not assume that inflation of reputations was widespread; it was simply a continuing undercurrent. The proof that, on the whole, the connoisseurs did not accede to this temptation is found in this fact: globally speaking, the canon of works attributed to many great masters shrank, as new methods of evaluation were stringently applied.
The
task of connoisseurs in shaping the accepted oeuvre of an individual
artist is crucial, for if we inadvertently rely on shop works or
forgeries to shape our overall image of an artist's work we blur the
image. Market pressures tend to bloat the (apparent) oeuvre of
an artist--sometimes approaching a kind of bulimia, since the falsely
attributed works tend eventually to be ousted
by knowledgeable opinion. The process of paring down may have an
unsettling effect on the public, as in the recent Rembrandt
deattributions where such favorites as the Man
in the Helmet
in Berlin (Staatliche Museen) and The
Polish Rider
in New York (Frick Collection) were demoted to the status of works of
followers of the master.
Some
have held that the rules of connoisseurship can be explicitly stated,
while others believe that it is more a matter of taste and
experience. Max J. Friedländer held that a connoisseur is
an art historian who does not talk much.v
The meaning of this saying is that through looking the connoisseur
accumulates a great fund of internal experience, which he brings
crucially to bear on a particular object. This does not mean
that the judgments made by the connoisseur are purely intuitive,
even though in their swiftness they may appear to be so, for he or she can
give reasons for the opinion that is offered.
Giovanni
Morelli ("Ivan Lermolieff").
There
is general agreement that the prince of connoisseurs was Giovanni
Morelli (1816-1891), whose activity has been compared to that of a
Sherlock Holmes or a Sigmund Freud.vi
He is one of the few art historians to merit an adjective that is
established in the English language: Morellian.vii
The words Wölfflinian or Panofskyian occasionally occur, but (as far
as I know) no one has ever used "Rieglesque" or
"Wickhoffian."
Morelli
was born in Verona of a Protestant family that was probably
ultimately French in origin.viii
Barred from local schools because of his religion, Morelli studied at
the cantonal school in Aarau, Switzerland, and then entered the
University of Munich, dedicating himself to medicine and natural
science. This education gave him a perfect command of the German
language. A satire he wrote on the Munich art world of his day
reveals his puckish humor.
Morelli never practiced medicine. In 1839 he proceeded to Paris where he divided his time between science and art, with numerous visits to the Louvre. His scientific pursuits led to a paper on dinosaurs, showing his interest in problems of classification and in distinguishing various degrees of difference in the wake of Georges Cuvier. At some point later in life he became acquainted with the physician Claude Bernard's "experimental method," an ideal he was to defend (without giving proper credit to its originator) in his mature writings. Gradually, Morelli's dedication to science ebbed, but not without leaving a lasting mark on his methods of aesthetic investigation.
Morelli never practiced medicine. In 1839 he proceeded to Paris where he divided his time between science and art, with numerous visits to the Louvre. His scientific pursuits led to a paper on dinosaurs, showing his interest in problems of classification and in distinguishing various degrees of difference in the wake of Georges Cuvier. At some point later in life he became acquainted with the physician Claude Bernard's "experimental method," an ideal he was to defend (without giving proper credit to its originator) in his mature writings. Gradually, Morelli's dedication to science ebbed, but not without leaving a lasting mark on his methods of aesthetic investigation.
During
the 1840s he lived mainly at Bergamo, composing pieces for German
periodicals and meditating on art. Repercussions from his
involvement in the Italian nationalist movement in 1848 caused
him to go into temporary exile north of the Alps. In 1860
Morelli was named a deputy in the Italian parliament; he became a
senator in 1873. The intersection of his official duties with his
interest in art involved him in the question of regulating export of
Italian works abroad; here he was ambivalent, sometimes decrying
exports, on other occasions maintaining that the visibility of Italian
paintings in other countries would foster esteem for his country and
its culture.
Thirty
years after his interest in art had first been kindled during his
student days in Munich, Morelli published his first art-historical
articles. His studies of works in the Borghese Gallery in Rome
appeared in the Zeitschrift
für bildende Kunst
in 1874-76. In 1880 a book distilling his conclusions regarding
Italian paintings in the galleries of Munich, Dresden, and Berlin
appeared in Leipzig.ix
A lively controversy ensued, as some German scholars indignantly
rejected his new attributions. Both the articles and the book were
attributed to "Ivan Lermolieff," ostensibly a Russian
savant. But this pseudonym is only his own name disguised, for
Ivan and Giovanni are both "John" while the first seven
letters of Lermolieff are an anagram of his own surname, appending
the characteristic Russian family suffix (-eff = -ev).x
The book also purports to be translated from Russian into German by
Johannes Schwarze, or "John Black." The Black surname
is a play on the word Morelli, "little Moor." In this
way Morelli wrapped himself in a double disguise. He first allowed
his real name to be used in an 1883 translation of his first book
into English, while maintaining the fiction for some time longer in
Germany.xi
Why
Morelli elected to use this double pseudonym to conceal his identity
has never been fully explained. Since his comments on
attribution were controversial, he may have wished to insulate his
political career from his art historical enterprise. While he
took his aesthetic inquiries in dead earnest, he must have recognized
that some of his associates in government would think them
dilettantish. His revelations that some works were
misattributed were bound to offend and outrage those with a
vested interest in maintaining the old labels. This clash of
opinions could lead to unpleasantness in social encounters, which he could avoid as long as his secret were kept. His pixieish side
took a mischievous delight in the effects of the deception. More
seriously, Morelli may have felt some diffidence about his Italian
origins, since in his day Italian scholarship had reached a low ebb.
An interesting comparison is with such women writers as George Eliot
and Georges Sand, who believed that they would receive more serious
attention if they took male names. In time he came to regard
the Lermolieff identity as almost separate from his own, attributing
to this individual a sureness of judgment that ranked him above that of
every other scholar. In any event, it is a strange irony that one
who devoted his scholarly career to inspecting the papers of works
traveling under false pretences should have chosen to hide his own identity.
Perhaps
one can go further: was the investigator himself a stable
personality? In the public mind, at least, Morelli succeeded in
dividing himself into two selves, Morelli and Lermolieff, only
attempting to unite them at the end of his life. It is a striking
fact that the 1880s saw the introduction, stemming mainly from the
French psychologist Pierre Janet (1859-1947), of the concept of
multiple personalities, which had been largely ignored up to that
point.
Morelli's
actual practices of attribution are clear enough. In some instances,
as in his vindication of the attribution of the Dresden Venus to
Giorgione, he used a combination of documentary and stylistic
evidence, a method closely akin to that of Rumohr (whom he admired)
before him. Yet Morelli's real innovation lay in a different
procedure, which he outlined in the essay on principles and method at
the head of his second book of 1890.xii
What he became famous--and notorious--for was his claim that the
touchstones of authenticity are not such major features as
composition or coloring. These can be cleverly simulated by a
pupil or later forger. Instead the imitator will slip up in the
handling of peripheral details, such as the ears or the fingers.
In focusing on these tell-tale signs Morelli seemed to turn
connoisseurship into a kind of detective story, an elaborate chess
game that the connoisseur plays at long distance with cunning
adversaries, the forger and the misattributer. His method
caused Morelli to be charged with not being interested in paintings
as a whole, a complaint he rebutted by arguing that it was precisely
to establish the overall identity of a particular painting that he
was conducting his exercises. After all, once we catch a
criminal through the analysis of fingerprints we do not incarcerate
only the fingers!
Morelli
held that getting the attributions straight was but a prelude to the
writing of a new, more accurate history of Italian art. Although he
never got around to composing this work, a few scattered remarks permit one
to hazard some conjecture of what it might look like. Morelli held
that each of the schools of Italian art developed organically,
responding like a plant to its environment. Each branch of art
follows a natural cycle from birth to maturity to decay. The
regional styles are strongly impressed by the character of the
people, so much so that influences from outside are of little
account. In order to clarify this regional character he appealed to
the analogy of local dialects, wherein Italy was particularly rich.
Morelli intended his feats of attribution as a first stage in a
larger program. Once correctly attributed through careful study in
situ, paintings could be grouped according to their creator in
monographs. These building blocks would then serve as the basis for the a truly
satisfactory history, but neither the master connoisseur nor his
followers realized this ambition.
Morelli's
concern with unmasking, with revealing impostors, recalls the
inquiries of Friedrich Nietzsche and Sigmund Freud. In fact
Freud possessed one of Morelli's books, and remarked on the
similarity of the Italian's search for revealing little clues and
the attention the psychoanalyst must pay to brief but telling
remarks. In their different ways a number of innovative writers of
the late nineteenth century insisted that what we conventionally
perceive is often not the real person. We must strike off the
mask and see the person as he or she is. And indeed Morelli's
method did alter forever our perception of some of the great masters
of Italian art by excluding the impostor-paintings that had inveigled
themselves into the oeuvre.
In 1761
the novelist Lawrence Sterne wrote playfully of the "Correggiescity"
of Correggio. At first sight this notion that each artist has an
essence so individual that it forms a category all of itself seems
extreme. Yet it goes to the heart of Morelli's project. He believed
that each body of work, each oeuvre of an individual artist was
sharply demarcated in its inner essence from any other. In effect
the oeuvre possesses a stable personality, indissolubly linked to the
personality of the artist him- or herself. Correggio must ever be
true to his own Correggiescity. Today, this confidence seems
excessive, for cannot even the greatest master have an "off day"
in which he or she commits the indiscretion of creating a work that
is not true to the artist's ultimate standards? The German painter
Max Liebermann used to say that art historians have the function of
saving artists from the consequences of their mistakes, by ruling
that inferior works are not actually by the person credited with
them.
Literary
scholars have created techniques of metrical analysis and word
frequency that help to settle disputed authorship of texts. Through
such methods it can be confirmed that St. Paul (or whoever wrote the
chief books in the Pauline corpus of the New Testament) is not the
author of the Epistle to the Hebrews since the Greek word patterns
are so different from those in the other writings attributed to Paul.
An interesting exercise would be to apply such methods to the corpus
of writings ostensibly written by Lermolieff and compare the results
with the corpus originally published by Morelli. If the writings of
Lermolieff (or more precisely, Lermolieff-Schwarze, since some
contribution must be allowed to the "translator") should
show a different pattern from that of the Morelli group, would this
indicate a bifurcation of personality, or just a very clever single
author? On the other hand, if the two groups of writings indicated
the same authorship, would this help to confirm Morelli's contention
that in the end genuine authorship cannot be concealed?
Some
modern critics would question whether the assumption of unity is a
necessary or even always a desirable quality in a significant work of
art. Thus the Russian literary critic Mikhail Bakhtin emphasized
the "polyphonic" complexity of Dostoevsky and other
authors, seeking to show how their vitality stems from the
incorporation and combination of textures that are strikingly
different.xiii
In this light perhaps Morelli's creation of an alter ego signified
an unconscious wish to subvert his own unitary concept of
creativity--an irony that would have been relished by Sigmund Freud
if not the conscious Morelli himself.
The
Morellian Legacy.
Morelli
wrote during a period that saw the ascendancy of positivism, the
belief that a sober, scientific approach could solve all problems,
without the intrusion of metaphysics. Accordingly, many who embraced
Morelli's methods did so under the impression that they were
scientific. Today they seem less so. Despite his claims to have
founded a reliable "experimental method," we can recognize
in Morelli the traditional figure of the art lover, a type that was
being shunted aside even during his lifetime by the new professional art
historian. Still, the application of Morellian standards of
connoisseurship did help to weed out many weak and inadequate works
that, falsely labeled, had been corrupting the oeuvre of many
masters.
A
similar housecleaning was undertaken for Greek art by Adolf
Furtwängler, who separated the reliable ancient copies of sculptures
from those that were poor or misidentified.xiv
Before his death in 1907, Furtwängler turned his attention to vase
painting, but with less spectacular results. The most sustained
application of Morellian method to Greek art was accomplished by the
British archaeologist Sir John Beazley (1885-1970), who rounded out
the oeuvre of hundreds of vase painters, inventing "names of
necessity" such as the Berlin Painter and "Elbows Out"
for personalities whose real names had not survived.xv
Recently Beazley's work has come under attack, in part for
transferring methods derived from Italian Renaissance painting to a
humbler field, but the critics have been rebutted.xvi
The
most visible pruning and reattributing occurred in the great public
collections of paintings in Europe. So thorough was the
housecleaning of European painting collections by the connoisseurs
that after World War II European scholars visiting American public
collections, where this task had been neglected in order to avoid
ruffling the sensibilities of recent donors, expressed shock that so
many inferior works could be passing under the names of the great
masters.
On
would expect that the process of sifting would also be evident in an
increasing stability of the rosters of accepted works found in
catalogues raisonnés. Indeed, this stabilization seems to have
taken place, as one can see by looking at the concordance tables of
recent catalogues of the works of such artists as Poussin and
Vermeer. However, this convergence of opinion may not constitute a
final vindication of the connoisseurship techniques stemming from
Morelli. For the work of many old masters, such as those just named,
is accompanied by reliable records of provenance, so that the
connoisseur's conclusions are supported by external evidence. In the
case of Rembrandt there have been several attempts to pare away
dross. The most recent, still ongoing, has been undertaken by a
commission--the Rembrandt Research Project--sustained by the Dutch
government.xvii
One instance, though an extravagant and atypical one, does give
pause--the corpus of drawings attributed to Michelangelo. In 1911-12
Karl Frey recognized 244 autograph drawings, a figure that Bernard
Berenson boosted to 288. In 1908-13 Henry Thode accepted 494 as
authentic. Charles de Tolnay, who devoted much of his life to
Michelangelo, ended by placing his imprimatur on no less than 630
(1975-80). Frederick Hartt, in 1971, accepted 465, while Michael
Hirst attained a high point of 785 (1988), in part by counting each
side of separate sheets as an individual item. It was left for
Alexander Perrig to call a drastic halt to this reckless expansionism, with a truly meager canon of only 24 drawings!xviii
After
the wave of positivism had passed, later connoisseurs gave a greater
role to intuition. Speaking for many, Max J. Friedländer said that
immediately on first seeing a work of an artist within his orbit he
knew whether it was authentic or not. Of
course, reasons could be given, but they came later. This immediacy
may support Carlo Ginzburg's claim that the act of connoisseurship
stems ultimately from the tracking skills of primitive hunters, who
must judge both surely and swiftly.
Friedländer's
claim also suggests that more investigation is needed on the elusive
concept of "eye." The role of quick judgment through
visual inspection is recognized in such different fields as military
tactics and billiards. And the contemporary critic Clement Greenberg
has repeatedly emphasized the role of the eye in selecting important
contemporary artists from the mass that are not destined to enjoy
lasting fame.
When
Morelli began his work, photographs of paintings were not widely
available. Engravings of famous works had achieved wide
circulation, but these clearly involved an interpretation, that of
the printmaker, imposed between the original and the scholar.
Morelli's work required intense study of the originals ("autopsy"),
and this emphasis was taken over by his disciple Bernard Berenson,
who would sometimes stand as long as an hour before a single painting
trying to fix in his memory each brush stroke and color tone.
Later, after Berenson had established himself in his villa of I
Tatti near Florence, he accumulated a large collection of
black-and-white photographs which he used to refresh his memory.
Today's widespread use of photographs as a substitute for
viewing the originals must be regarded as a step backwards. (A
possibly apocryphal story about Adolph Goldschmidt, the great student
of medieval ivory carvings, alleges that he once declined to inspect
an original brought to him by a collector, saying "Send me a
photo.") For many decades after their first introduction
photographs were only in black and white (and even today the color
ones are generally unreliable, and some of the most seductive are
farther from the originals than others judged by publishers to be
"less exciting": les belles sont infidèles). In
any event, this reliance on monochrome images constituted an ironic
victory for the Florentine concept of disegno
or composition as against the Venetian emphasis on color.
Even now a comprehensive history of color in painting is
lacking.
Today,
in addition to photography, the critical perceptions of the
connoisseur can be extended and confirmed by scientific
tests--x-rays, radiocarbon, fluoroluminiscence and other types
of measurement. Connoisseurship is still needed in the museum,
gallery, and auction house. The main value of scientific tests
is to show a lack of concordance in date, as in Van Meegeren's
twentieth-century forgeries of Vermeer's seventeenth-century
masterworks. However if a modern forger attempts a fake Picasso
or Chagall using contemporary materials and techniques, it may be
that connoisseurship of the traditional type is the only resource
capable of exposing the imposture. And--despite the
Michelangelo conundrum noted above--students derive great insight
from working with original drawings and striving to reach their own
conclusions about authorship.
Bernard
Berenson.
Once
overrated, Bernard Berenson (1865-1959) is probably now too little
esteemed.xix
While he never taught at a university and failed to measure up to the
professional canons that had emerged in Germany and the United States, among
the general public Berenson long enjoyed the status of "Mr. Art
History." As Edmund Wilson instructed the educated in
literature while Walter Lippmann performed the same service in public
affairs, so Berenson offered guidance in the realm of the old
masters. For cultivated amateurs, especially those making their
pilgrimage to the hallowed sites of Italy, perusing his books was de
rigueur. In more recent years, however, he has been attacked as a
pure formalist, an antidemocratic elitist, a commercialist whose
evaluations were swayed by the art market, and as an unreconstructed
Eurocentrist.
Born to
a Jewish family in Lithuania and raised in poverty in Boston, he
assimilated easily to his adopted country and class, absorbing the
high seriousness cherished by the Brahmins of the Massachusetts
metropolis. More specific influences included the pragmatism of
William James, the orientalism of Ernest Fenollosa, and the
aestheticism (imported from England) of Walter Pater.
A child
prodigy, Bernard Berenson early captured the admiration of
influential Bostonians. Eventually he was taken up by the very
wealthy Isabella Stewart Gardner, whose private collection was
to become the impressive Gardner Museum. This maecenas
supported her protégé during several years of study and travel in
Europe. There he composed (in a somewhat cloying style) four
short books on the Italian schools of painting that enjoyed a great
vogue in America and England. Subsequently, Berenson himself
referred to them, not entirely humorously, as the "four
gospels."xx
The
general picture these narratives present is one of regional schools
which rise, reach their peak, and decline. Berenson had little use
for mannerist and baroque art, which he relegated to the category of
decline. His method is a systematization of that of Morelli. He
recognized three kinds of materials for historical study:
contemporary documents, tradition, and the works of art themselves.xxi
In the end, it is the examination of the works themselves by the
trained connoisseur that is decisive. In the discrimination of
authorship he recognized the familiar Morellian features of the ears
and the hands, to which he added the folds and the landscape. Less
reliable traits were the hair, the eyes, the nose, and the mouth.
Finally, the cranium, the chin, the structure and movement of the
human figure, the architecture, the color, and the chiaroscuro
were--however enjoyable for themselves--of no value in determining
authorship.
A
hundred years later, after many advances of scholarship, it is not
easy to grasp the once-riveting qualities of these four books. In
their concise texts Berenson not only passed in review the major
painters of the various parts of Italy, but he offered principles of
art appreciation intended to have universal application. In the
pivotal volume on the Florentine
Painters of the Italian Renaissance
(1896) Berenson held that medieval art is merely semiotic: once we
have deciphered the symbols, there is no further gain. With Giotto,
however, something of great significance is added. Art works of this
new stamp are capable of "giving tactile values to retinal
impressions." The meaning of this sense of tactile values is
not entirely clear, but the American scholar seems to have grounded
it in the idea of Einfühlung
or empathy championed by the German psychological writer Theodor
Lipps. According to Berenson's theory, we derive a sense of
solace and well being, what he termed "life-enhancement,"
through our identification with the figures and scenes we see
depicted. In all likelihood Berenson took the notion of
life-enhancement from the philosophers Friedrich Nietzsche and Henri
Bergson, then approaching their peak of popularity.
Contemporary
French art, with its tendencies to formalism, was not absent from his
thoughts. The young Berenson particularly admired the art of Edgar
Degas. But there were limits. Although the author of The
Florentine Painters of the Renaissance
allowed for the effect of pure line, he consistently tied the
expression of tactile values, and the "ideated sensations"
to which these gave rise, to representations of the human body. For
this reason he vehemently rejected abstract art.
Despite
the assurance with which they were proffered, his theories echo
late-nineteenth-century Continental trends, displaying not only the
methods of Morelli but also contact with the German psychological and
perceptual tradition that undergirded the work of Heinrich Wölfflin.
These German ideas came to him in part through reading and in part
through personal contact with the artists Adolf Hildebrand and
Hermann Obrist.
Berenson
was physically slight and frail, a classic neurasthenic of the late
nineteenth century. A concept of art that offered a therapeutic
compensation ("life-enhancement") for his own physical
deficiencies held a strong personal appeal. In this he was not
alone. Such therapeutic virtues would appeal to two groups who
responded to his writings: the leisured travelers--some
of them hypochondriacs ostensibly voyaging on doctor's orders--who
filled European resorts and art cities, and the captains of industry,
who sought soothing distractions after a day of stress on the stock
market or in the board room. As has frequently been noted,
Berenson's interests fit all too well into the aspirations of the
elite of the beau monde, much of it consisting of the newly wealthy
who needed a cachet of culture that only expensive, old objects could
provide.
Eventually
he established a durable partnership with the English dealer Joseph
Duveen, and the two were able to obtain high prices for many Italian
Renaissance paintings in America. In time Berenson became a
slave to his own lavish lifestyle conducted at his villa in
Settignano.xxii
Taken up with a life of hobnobbing with the rich and famous,
he more and more subordinated scholarship to the money-making side of
connoisseurship. Since his death it has been charged that
Berenson altered or "massaged" his attributions to
increase the value of the paintings by making their origins seem more
exalted than they were.xxiii
These claims of venality seem exaggerated, but it should be
remembered that at a time when many old master paintings were up
for sale, commercial temptations could lead to distortions of
attribution. (Today, with most old masters off the market, such
temptations arise more commonly in connection with the works of
modern artists.) In the context of his time, Berenson's attribution
policies were not excessive, and were probably more scrupulous than
most of his fellow experts.
Because
Berenson had adjusted so well to his era, it is not surprising that
his stock fell precipitously--probably too far--after his death.
As a theorist he is probably best regarded as a transitional figure,
whose influence was destined to fade with the internationalization
of German scholarship.
Berenson
seems to have anticipated and dreaded this fate. Carefully
monitoring trends emanating from across the Alps, he bitterly
resisted the rehabilitation of late-antique art undertaken by the
Viennese art historians Riegl and Wickhoff. He planned a major
refutation of it, his monograph on Decline and Recovery in the
Figural Arts; only fragments of this projected magnum opus were
completed. Although in his youth he owed much to German studies of
the psychology of perception, as he grew older he became increasingly
hostile to the German tradition, going so far as to deplore the 1930s
Transatlantic Migration of German scholars to the United
States as a corrupting influence.
Moreover,
after some early interest in the works of Degas, Cézanne, and
Matisse, Berenson developed an aversion to modern art.xxiv
Holding his own emphasis on formal qualities in large part
responsible (he claimed too much), he deplored the formalism that
undergirded writings favoring modern works. But the rot went much
deeper. The whole of modern society had gone astray, he held,
becoming decadent. Advanced modern art, especially abstract art, was
an appalling symptom of the decay. In this way Berenson abandoned
his earlier emphasis on aesthetic qualities in favor of a censorious
moral stance. Moreover, if modern art is a symptom, and not a cause,
of decay, how could opposing it in the name of a return to classical
values arrest the process of decline?
Even in
the study of Renaissance works Berenson's thought focused not so much
on historical evolution, but on the attractions of an arcadian
dreamland of the past--in his case located in Italy during the
fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. Like his fellow cultural
critics José Ortega y Gasset and T. S. Eliot, he came to practice a
kind of "negative classicism," extolling the virtues of the
past as a contrast with the tawdry present. His interest in the art
of the early middle ages, which he excoriated as life-diminishing,
lay solely in using it as a parallel to twentieth-century art. The
underlying ethos of decadence, he implied, was the same. Both were
antithetical to the spirit of humanism inherent in classical and
Renaissance art.
Of the
"position papers" Berenson published after World War II in
an effort to sum up his thought, Aesthetics
and History
(1948) is the most substantial. The program he advocates for art
history is a highly selective one. Although he recognizes that the
arts of the great civilizations of Asia are major achievements, they
are not for us; acquiring the linguistic and other erudition required
to evaluate such alien products would be too laborious, diverting
one's energies away from the works of art themselves. Even the arts
of Germany and Spain, he held, lie essentially outside the
mainstream, and may be safely neglected except by specialists of
those countries. In addition, too much preoccupation with meaning
and social context is unwise; it takes us away from building our
"House of Life" through concentration on the genuine
masterpieces. Berenson concludes his observations with remarks
intended to introduce his unfinished monograph on early medieval art:
"[w[e shall not lose sight of the fact that we are absorbed in
the study of art not in health but in disease, in other words that we
are investigating the pathology of art."xxv
Aspiring to reverence as a sage, he seems more of a curmudgeon,
bitterly disappointed that twentieth-century art was not to his
liking, and blasting earlier forms of art insidiously revived to
buttress the products of our own purported decline.
Viewed
from the end of the century in which Berenson was in some sense an
unwilling participant, his faults loom large. Yet can we really
begrudge him his love of the Italian Renaissance? In our own day
another type of historical partiality may be occurring with the
exaltation--in the auction rooms and among the general public--of
impressionism and postimpressionism. It may be that ordinary
art lovers need to focus on a single era where they feel at home.
For when all is said and done, the aesthetic neutrality of the
confirmed art historian is an austere creed, enjoining an impartial
"democracy of epochs." This impartiality is not to
everyone's taste, but if art history is to retain the character of a
discipline, and not a mere adjunct to the worlds of commerce and
spectacle, it must not cast aside the achievements of the historical
point of view which have reduced subjectivity while broadening our
horizons.
Today, some lament that the techniques of connoisseurship are in decline. However, Christie's Education offers an MA in the History of Art and the Art Market that includes a seminar on connoisseurship. This comprises "the critical skills needed to look at art, write about art, research and evaluate works, including handling and viewing art objects and visiting artists’ studios, conservation labs and museums."
Today, some lament that the techniques of connoisseurship are in decline. However, Christie's Education offers an MA in the History of Art and the Art Market that includes a seminar on connoisseurship. This comprises "the critical skills needed to look at art, write about art, research and evaluate works, including handling and viewing art objects and visiting artists’ studios, conservation labs and museums."
Aftermath.
In some
respects Berensonian connoisseurship represents the apotheosis of
the formal approach. Although he had converted to Roman
Catholicism, the religious message inherent in most of the paintings
he examined held little interest for him, being superseded by
"tactile values."
A
different, and more radical version of this formalism appeared in
England with the concept of "significant form" of Clive
Bell and Roger Fry. Affiliated with the Bloomsbury group, these
scholars had a positive response to modern art, above all the work of
Cézanne. From Cézanne the path led on to abstract art.
In order to account for this trend the British theorists collapsed
the dichotomy between form and meaning--holding that the form is
the meaning.
Although
the Bloomsbury outcome was probably foreseeable, it would be wrong to
identify connoisseurship and Berenson with the radical formalism of
Bell and Fry. Earlier savants still recognized the role of subject
matter, even though they may have seemed to relegate it to a
subordinate place. But they retained their faith in the humanism
inherited from the Renaissance--a loyalty that many twentieth-century
artists and their advocates were to cast aside.
i
Considerazioni
sulla pittura; pubblicate per la prima volta da Dariano Marucchi,
con il commento di Luigi Salerno,
Rome: Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei, 1956.
iii
Carol Gibson-Wood, "Jonathan Richardson and the Rationalization
of Connoisseurship," Art
History,
7:1 (1984), 38-56 (cited: p. 40).
iv
For discussions of important aspects of collecting (where much
research remains to be done), see Joseph Alsop, The
Rare Art Traditions: The History of Art Collecting and Its Linked
Phenomena,
New York: Harper & Row, 1982; Antoine Schnapper, Le
Géant, la licorne, la tulipe: Collections françaises au XVIIe
siècle,
I, Paris: Flammarion, 1988; Krzysztof Pomian, Collectors
and Curiosities: Paris and Venice, 1500-1800,
trans. by Elizabeth Wiles-Porter, Oxford: 1990. For some years The
Burlington Magazine
has been including specialist articles on historical collections;
see also Journal
of the History of Collections
(Oxford University Press, 1989- ).
v
For this genial writer's credo, see Max J. Friedländer, On
Art and Connoisseurship,
translated by Tancred Borenius, Boston: Beacon Press, 1960 (first
published in 1942 by Bruno Cassirer in Oxford).
vi
Carlo Ginzburg, "Clues: Roots of an Evidential Paradigm,"
in his Clues,
Myths and the Historical Method,
trans. by John and Anne Tedeschi, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press, 1989, 96-123.
viii
A critical biography of this savant is still lacking. See, however,
Matteo Panzeri and Giulio Orazio Bravi, eds., La
Figura e l'opera di Giovanni Morelli: materiali di ricerca,
Bergamo: Biblioteca Civica Angelo Mai, 1987; Hans Ebert, Donata
Levi, and Giacomo Agosti, La
Figura e l'opera di Giovanni Morelli: studi e ricerche,
Bergamo: Biblioteca Civica Angelo Mai, 1987; and Carol Gibson-Wood,
Studies
in Connoisseurship from Vasari to Morelli,
New York: Garland, 1988, pp. 166-237.
ix
Die
Werke italienischer Meister in den Galerien von München, Dresden
und Berlin: Ein kritischer Versuch von Ivan Lermolieff; aus dem
Russischen übersetzt von Dr. Johannes Schwarze,
Leipzig: E. A. Seemann, 1880.
x
The correct form in Russian would have been Lermolov.
xi
Italian
Masters in German Galleries: A Critical Essay on the Italian
Pictures in the Galleries of Munich, Dresden, Berlin,
trans. Louise M. Richter, London: George Bell and Street, 1883.
xii
"Ivan Lermolieff," Kunstkritische
Studien über italienische Malerei: Die Galerien Borghese und Doria
Pamfili in Rom,
Leipzig: F. A. Brockhaus, 1890. The essay also appears in the
English version: Giovanni Morelli (Ivan Lermolieff), Italian
Painters: Critical Studies of Their Works: The Borghese and
Doria-Pamfili in Rome,
trans. by Constance Jocelyn Ffoulkes, London: John Murray, 1900
("Principles and Method," pp. 3-63.
xiii
Gary Saul Morson and Caryl Emerson, Mikhail
Bakhtin: Creation of a Prosaics,
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1990, pp. 231-68.
xiv
Adolf Furtwängler, Masterpieces
of Greek Sculpture,
ed. and trans. by Eugénie Sellers, New York: Scribner, 1895.
xv
Apart from his many articles and monographs, see Beazley's great
collections: Attic
Black-Figured Vase Painters,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956; Attic
Red-Figured Vase Painters,
2nd ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1942. The latter work contains
more than 15,000 items.
xvi
For the attacks and rebuttal of them, see Martin Robertson, The
Art of Vase Painting in Classical Athens,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992, pp. 3-6. For Beazley's
place in the earlier history of vase-painting research, see R. M.
Cook, Greek
Painted Pottery,
Chicago: Quadrangle Books, 1960, pp. 288-330.
xvii
The volumes of Josua Bruyn et al., A
Corpus of Rembrandt Paintings,
began to appear in 1982 (The Hague: Stichtung Foundation Rembrandt
Research Project). Despite the impressive credentials of the
participants, other qualified experts have expressed disagreement
regarding the status of particular works. This lack of consensus
suggests that an irreducible element of subjectivity remains in
connoisseurship.
xviii
Alexander Perrig, Michelangelo's
Drawings: The Science of Attribution,
translated by Michael Joyce, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991.
xix
Ernest Samuels, Bernard
Berenson: The Making of a Connoisseur,
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979; idem, Bernard
Berenson: The Making of a Legend,
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987. These two volumes constitute one of the best biographies of an art
historian that has yet appeared.
xx
Originally published in 1894-1907, they were later collected into a
single volume, The
Italian Painters of the Renaissance,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930. In the first publication, each
volume was completed by a list of works accepted by Berenson as
authentic. In the 1930s these rosters were separated, revised and
enlarged, and gathered together in a separate volume, Italian
Pictures of the Renaissance: A List of the Principal Artists and
Their Works with an Index of Places,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1932. This book classifies and locates
some 15,000 works, a stupendous undertaking that no single scholar
would dare to attempt today.
xxi
Bernhard [sic] Berenson, "Rudiments of Connoisseurship (A
Fragment)," The
Study and Criticism of Italian Art: Second Series,
London: George Bell, 1902, pp. 111-48.
xxii
See the astringent comments of Meyer Schapiro, "Mr. Berenson's
Values," Encounter,
16 (January 1961), 57-65.
xxiii
Colin Simpson, Artful
Partners: Bernard Berenson and Joseph Duveen,
New York: Macmillan, 1987.
xxiv
On Berenson and modernity, see the perceptive analysis of Mary Ann
Calo, Bernard
Berenson and the Twentieth Century,
Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1994 (which perhaps
overstates the contribution of his ideas to modern art criticism).
No comments:
Post a Comment