For all
their brilliance, energy, and persuasiveness, Vasari and Winckelmann clung to a narrow classical taste that by definition banished most of
the world's art to the realm of barbarism. In order to access
a broader range of aesthetic phenomena, a major change in orientation
had to occur.
The new approaches addressed in this and the following chapters of this book could not
have occurred without the rise of the romanticism. This great sea
change in sensibility and in creative expression is so complex
that it merits study in terms of its leading aspects, and not simply as a
unitary phenomenon unfolding in strict chronological sequence.i
This exposition requires a postponement, until the next chapter, of
the discussion of the chief trends in narrative art historiography.
The
roots of the romanticism go back to the early eighteenth
century. Some historians even trace the ultimate origins of the
trend back to classical antiquity, when the mysterious Longinus
(first century of our era) advocated the cultivation of sublime
effects in literature. And even earlier, the philosopher Plato, with
his concept of love as longing for the ideal and his utopian notion
of the ideal republic, had anticipated key romantic themes. At the
other end of the time scale, suvivals of romanticism have been
detected in the late twentieth century, as seen in the emotionality
of rock music and the free-form paintings of neo-expressionism. It
may be that in fact romanticism is a perennial state of mind, waxing stronger
during some periods and fading during others. If so, it was
providential that it burgeoned in the opening decades of
the nineteenth century, when it demolished the hegemony of the Neo-classical style, opening the way for a pluralistic approach to
the world's cultural achievements.
The
complexity of this period of triumph--romanticism par excellence--reflected a number of social factors: the question of the proper
organization of society raised by the Enlightenment and the French
Revolution; European imperialist expansion abroad and political
rivalries at home; and--above all--rapid technological change as the industrial revolution relentlessly progressed on the
continent of Europe.
In the
sciences this was the age of Cuvier and Comte, of Faraday and Darwin;
it was also the time when the steamship, the telegraph, and the
railroad began to bind the world together. To many observers, the
cascade of useful innovations in science and technology made the arts
seem trivial by comparison.ii
To counter this dismissive tendency, those who still held the fine
arts in high esteem were compelled to generate new arguments in their
favor. Some advocates sought to invest the arts with a quasireligious aura. In a
period in which dogmatic verities were increasingly subject to doubt,
art could become a surrogate for religion, pouring balm on the wound
inflicted by the loss of faith.iii
Cultural conservatives, unwilling to abandon tradition and more
sanguine about the prospects of religious revival, held that art
could play a valuable ancillary in this process of spiritual regeneration.iv In fact new schools of pietistic painting--the German Nazarenes and their
counterparts in other countries--arose to fill this perceived need. Yet other observers, more practically inclined, stressed the civilizing
power of the visual arts; tastefully displayed, art objects became,
so to speak, the guarantors of the respectability of the bourgeois
home. Eventually, this trend gave rise to the profession of interior
decorator and the countless magazines catering to the aspirations of
the house-proud middle class.
Not
only did science and technology force the arts into a defensive
posture--albeit often a creative one--they invaded the realm of art
itself. In ceramics, furniture, and other crafts, new processes of
production began to take hold. Economic advantages notwithstanding,
mass production and mass consumption tended to lower aesthetic
quality, a lesson painfully learned in the great international
exhibition held in London in 1851.
As a response to the situation, the Arts and Crafts Movement arose under the aegis of William Morris in the later decades of the nineteenth century. The intent was to reverse the degradation of taste by creating objects that, even though ordinary, were well-made and beautiful.v Yet there was a catch, so to speak. Implicitly, the new sense of the dignity of the so-called minor arts called into question the old idea of the absolute superiority of the fine arts of architecture, painting, and sculpture--a cardinal feature of the system of the arts inherited from the Renaissance.
As a response to the situation, the Arts and Crafts Movement arose under the aegis of William Morris in the later decades of the nineteenth century. The intent was to reverse the degradation of taste by creating objects that, even though ordinary, were well-made and beautiful.v Yet there was a catch, so to speak. Implicitly, the new sense of the dignity of the so-called minor arts called into question the old idea of the absolute superiority of the fine arts of architecture, painting, and sculpture--a cardinal feature of the system of the arts inherited from the Renaissance.
The
subjectivity of taste was more and more conceded, however tacitly and
reluctantly. In France admirers of the official salon paintings, with their
elaborate mythological and religious themes, believed that the display
and purchase of such works helped to hold the line against the
barbarism invading the new industrial society. Conversely, advocates
of advanced, experimental art maintained that the pompous "machines"
of the salon, with their lifeless mimicry of outmoded styles and
subject matter, were themselves symptoms of declining standards. In
their view, the new progressive art of the avant-garde best reflected what was best in
contemporary society.
All
these changes notwithstanding, art itself flourished mightily; and even today, nineteenth-century art is a powerful magnet for the crowds that continue to flock to museums and galleries that
display it. Moreover, the new climate of uncertainty and questioning
fostered a demand for lectures and writings addressing these issues.
As never before, art historiography flourished--accounting for the common misperception
that this branch of scholarship actually originated during this
period, instead of much earlier, as we have seen.
The
Emergence of Aesthetic Relativism.
Matters
of taste had not always been as uniform and predictable as the
defenders of the sanctity of Renaissance norms were wont to claim. There was more
variety on the ground than the ideal suggested. During the middle ages and after
Europeans had been attracted to Islamic art; textiles and ceramics of
Muslim manufacture were cherished possessions of church treasuries,
in large measure because in keeping with Islamic avoidance of
figuration they had little detectable iconography that was
specifically Muslim.vi
The conquests in the Americas had yielded booty in the form of
pre-Columbian art, capturing, for a time, the admiration of
Europeans.vii
As regards Asia, the European eighteenth century saw a
sustained enthusiasm for things Chinese, not only in the form of
imports but also in works produced at home; however, the motifs
imitated were selected and adjusted to suit European, essentially
rococo tastes.viii
In various ways, though, these "exotic" forms were cordoned
off from European art, or neutralized by partial
incorporation. When all is said and done, it seems that
aesthetic choice--even when it was allowed--took the form of a
selection from European models.
Ultimately,
the foundations for change were to be laid in the conceptual sphere.
One underlying principle is the notion of organic unity.ix
This biological metaphor had long been honored in the analysis of
individual works, and now it was applied to society and its relation
to the arts. It was held that each civilization brought forth
the cultural objects that were appropriate to it. In a telling
metaphor, Jacob Burckhardt remarked that one cannot expect a fig tree
to put forth grapes, nor a vine figs. Of course a civilization is
not a tree. Still we feel that some important issues are being
addressed here. Even in advanced industrial societies there are
common characteristics--family resemblances--that link the artefacts
of a given period. We recognize this when we speak of the
nineteen-twenties or the 'fifties as producing objects that have a
recognizable period style.
One of
the features of Enlightenment thought as a whole was a healthy dose
of relativism. Thus while it was generally held that aesthetic
standards were absolute and knowable, a subcurrent acknowledged an
element of the unknowable, perhaps even the irrational in aesthetic
pleasure. Some writers chose to affirm this aspect in the
formula "Je ne sais quoi" ("I known not what").x
Spread by a number of French writers on aesthetics, this idea
originated in Renaissance Italy, where in 1541 Agnolo Firenzuola
spoke of the grace of women as residing in "un non so che."
One is reminded also of Vasari's grazia,
that special gift of God and nature; informing the works of the
greatest artists, it could not be attained simply by adherence to the
rules. From the continent this idea that licence might be
permitted under exceptional circumstances spread to Britain. In his
verse Essay
on Criticism
(1711), Alexander Pope had noted that Great Wits sometimes may
gloriously offend/And rise to Faults true Criticks dare not mend;/ .
. . And snatch a Grace beyond the Reach of Art."xi
For
Pope, as with Vasari, this subversive implications of this idea were kept in check within the
bounds of a classicizing aesthetic: only "Great Wits" are
accorded such licence. But as it spread, the principle of the Je ne
sais quoi tended to release this idea from its bonds, universalizing
it by suggesting that all works of art may have significant elements
that cannot be precisely elucidated in words and may even transcend
rational processes altogether. This tendency, of course, was to
find an appropriate place in the great mosaic of romanticism, with
its stress on the supreme importance of intuition and feeling over
against the cold processes of reason.
An old
theme, familiar to the Greeks, was that art works act as a form of
magic. In Renaissance Europe the hermetic tradition attempted
to formulate rules for the separation of white magic (good) from black magic (bad) and to show how the former could work for human good.
Giordano Bruno (1548-1600) had adumbrated a way in which this
approach could be applied to art.
Some later thinkers placed the idea under the emblem of the Circean principle.xii Circe, it will be remembered, was a powerful sorceress who enchanted men, turning them into beasts at her beck and call. Art works, of course, do not make us beasts but they may captivate us in a fashion somewhat akin to Circe's magic. Today we even express this notion in certain "sunken" metaphors. We may speak of an "enthralling" play, derived from a word meaning to enslave. Other critics may refer to a performance as "riveting," implying that one is fixed to one's seat. "I couldn't put the book down" means that one has lost control. One can even imply annihilation: "that painting is dynamite; it just blew me away." Such comments do indeed reflect psychic realities, and as writers on art found themselves confronted with a larger, more disparate public such "unsophisticated" responses had to be anticipated, and to some respect catered to. Earlier critical theories, created to meet the needs of a narrower, more aristocratic audience, had not faced this problem.
Some later thinkers placed the idea under the emblem of the Circean principle.xii Circe, it will be remembered, was a powerful sorceress who enchanted men, turning them into beasts at her beck and call. Art works, of course, do not make us beasts but they may captivate us in a fashion somewhat akin to Circe's magic. Today we even express this notion in certain "sunken" metaphors. We may speak of an "enthralling" play, derived from a word meaning to enslave. Other critics may refer to a performance as "riveting," implying that one is fixed to one's seat. "I couldn't put the book down" means that one has lost control. One can even imply annihilation: "that painting is dynamite; it just blew me away." Such comments do indeed reflect psychic realities, and as writers on art found themselves confronted with a larger, more disparate public such "unsophisticated" responses had to be anticipated, and to some respect catered to. Earlier critical theories, created to meet the needs of a narrower, more aristocratic audience, had not faced this problem.
A
feature that tended to divide the neo-classicists from their romantic
brethren was their attitude towards line and color respectively.xiii
Following the Florentine tradition crystallized by Vasari, and
reinforced by the study of ancient marbles, the neo-classicists
tended to exalt line, as the vehicle of reasoned perception, over
color. For the romantics it was just the opposite: whether
subtle or intense, color reigned supreme as the conveyer of feeling.
This conflict has its roots in the sixteenth century in the contrast
between Florence (line) and Venice (color). Yet Venice failed
to produce theoreticians of sufficient stature to defend its
preference. Towards the end of the seventeenth century, however, a
more evenly balanced version of this debate emerged. In France
the followers of Poussin, who defended the classic
principle of the supremacy of line, disputed with the adherents of
Rubens, who supported his magnificent example as a colorist.
With
reference to the eighteenth century, changing discourse strategies in
writings about art and aesthetics require somewhat closer attention.
The first question has to do with the criteria whereby the quality of
art works was judged. For much of the eighteenth century cultivated
opinion clung to the notion that the rules of "good taste" were absolute. Invariable and universal they could in principle be acquired
by anyone with the patience and sensitivity to do so. Bad taste,
most blatantly represented by the horrors of the Middle
Ages, had to be shunned. Whether critics followed the older
Vasari model or the newer Winckelmann one, there was general
agreement on the underlying aesthetic norms. As the century drew to
a close, however, this confidence began to give way. Daringly, some advanced
thinkers and writers insisted that the monuments of the Middle Ages
deserved attention in their own right.xiv
The
establishment first tried containment. This upstart rival to good
taste might be allowed only as a kind jeu d'esprit, as when
writers remarked ironically of "Gothick excellences"--implying
that they were not excellences at all. However, the emergence of the
concept of the sublime, alongside the traditional veneration for the
beautiful, raised the awful prospect that there might in fact be two
truths in art, rather than one.
The
problem of dualism could be solved--very drastically--by simply
inverting the hierarchy. Arts that appeal to the sublime principle
are the highest, with the merely beautiful ones standing on a lower level.
Augustus Welby Northmore Pugin (1812-1852) and other enthusiasts for
the Gothic revival attempted to preserve their judgmentalism by
simply reversing it: Gothic is good, Renaissance bad.
Well
before Pugin wrote, however, an increasing number of observers began
to suspect, often uneasily, that more than one yardstick was needed.
Sympathetic study of a medieval cathedral demanded criteria different
from those appropriate for a Greek temple. This new aesthetic
relativism found support in the theory of the Baltic German Johann
Gottfried von Herder (1744-1803), who proposed that all cultures had
produced intellectual creations that are worthy of our interest.xv
At the same time these creations are highly specific; as he remarked
in 1774, "Every nation has its center of happiness in itself."
The key to this national uniqueness, Herder believed, is language,
which condenses the essence of a people.
Herder
and those who followed him believed strongly in the organic wholeness
of art. Yet at the same time they affirmed that art manifested itself differently in different times and places. Instead of lamenting
these variations as departures from a single universal standard,
which was basically the previous view, diversity should be
celebrated. In his own way Herder was a precursor of today's
multiculturalism.
In the
practice of art, as distinct from the way in which it was regarded,
the opening chapter in the rise of the new relativism was the battle
between the neo-classic and romantic styles. The coexistence of two
styles, each exalted by its champions as the only appropriate
vehicle of the sentiments of the age, was an unprecedented situation.
The
Sublime.
The
kernel of this idea goes back to an essay on literary criticism, On
the Sublime,
attributed to Longinus, a Greek rhetorician writing under the Roman
empire. To put the matter in a nutshell, our response to the sublime
is evoked by the presence of two factors: vastness of scale and
vehemence of the emotion. It is easier to state the effects of the
sublime than to define it. "The true sublime, by some virtue of
its nature, elevates us; uplifted with a sense of proud possession,
we are filled with joyful pride, as if we ourselves had produced the
very thing we had heard."xvi
The
Renaissance was familiar with the effects of transport, the
marvelous, and of magic that are integral to Longinus' concept, but
it did not recognize the sublime as an autonomous aesthetic category.
This development was left for English writers in the eighteenth
century.xvii
The essayist Joseph Addison (1672-1719) influentially addressed the
matter, though he tended to prefer the term greatness. "By
greatness," he states, "I do not mean the bulk of any
single object, but the largeness of the whole view considered as one
piece."xviii
Contemplation of the unbounded views of greatness flings us into "a
pleasing astonishment." The examples he gives come from the
contemplation of nature: "a troubled ocean, a heaven adorned
with stars and meteors, or a spacious landscape cut into rivers,
woods, rocks, and meadows."
At this
stage the concept of the visual sublime seems to have been restricted
to our experience of nature--works of art did not provoke the
emotion. However, a bridge to art may be detected landscape
architecture, which, though a human artifact, could be contrived in
such a way as to elicit a sublime or picturesque response. However
this may be, the definitive step of extending the sublime concept to
painting was taken by the painter-connoisseur Jonathan Richardson
(1665-1745). His views are more evident in criticism of particular
paintings, in which he relished free brush strokes, than in any
general theory.
That
lack was made up by Edmund Burke (1729-1797), now best known from his
later career as a British parliamentarian and political thinker.
This Anglo-Irish writer offered a comprehensive account of the
sublime in A
Philosophical Enquiry into the Origins of Our Ideas about the Sublime
and the Beautiful
(1757; revised ed., 1759).xix
Shifting the discussion from the realms of rhetoric (particular sets
of words) and visual display (scenes provided by nature and human
artifice), Burke grounded the contrast of the beautiful and the
sublime in the response of the observer--in the twin emotions of
pleasure and pain. Beautiful works gain our approbation by offering
the pleasing reassurance that the world is a comfortable place, where
we can readily comprehend our own situation. But sublime works
induce a shivering sense of the uncanny, even of the terrible and
repulsive. We are fearful, but since we suffer no real pain,
but only the suggestion of it, our sense of dread yields to one of
delight.
As Tom
Furniss has recently shown, it was not Burke's intention to upset the
established patterns of eighteenth-century sociey or aesthetics.xx
But without foreseeing the result, he opened for later investigators
a broad avenue for enlarging the scope of art history by making
medieval and "Oriental" works worthy objects of study.
Beauty they might lack, but sublimity they often possessed.
Hollywood has made billions from horror movies. So Burke was onto something with his concept of the transformation of threatened pain into delight. We choose not to live solely in a "vanilla" world of soothing experiences; we also have a need to be frightened. Of course few major works consist solely of either beautiful or sublime moments. The two choices rather represent a scale of aesthetic gambits in which the artist may choose an intermediate strategy, mingling pleasing beauty with striking sublimity. Towards the end of the eighteenth century some writers posited that the term "picturesque" might aptly describe an intermediate position between the two poles of the beautiful and the sublime.
Hollywood has made billions from horror movies. So Burke was onto something with his concept of the transformation of threatened pain into delight. We choose not to live solely in a "vanilla" world of soothing experiences; we also have a need to be frightened. Of course few major works consist solely of either beautiful or sublime moments. The two choices rather represent a scale of aesthetic gambits in which the artist may choose an intermediate strategy, mingling pleasing beauty with striking sublimity. Towards the end of the eighteenth century some writers posited that the term "picturesque" might aptly describe an intermediate position between the two poles of the beautiful and the sublime.
The
idea of the sublime was taken up by no less a figure than the
philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). His early Observations
on the Feeling of the Sublime and the Beautiful
date from 1764; he returned more conclusively to the matter in his
Critique
of Judgment
(1790). According to Kant beauty and sublimity are both predicates
of the aesthetic judgment.xxi
But they differ in that beauty is concerned with the form, that is
the boundedness of an object, while the sublime involves an
experience of boundlessness. The sublime is "absolutely great,"
by comparison with which everything else is small. The sublime
experience differs from estimation in terms of numbers because it is
a matter of imagination and intuition that stretches the very
boundaries of Reason.xxii
The
combined effect of Burke and Kant was to establish a two-source
scheme in which the beautiful and the sublime are equal in dignity,
though different in effects. The importance of this breach with the
monistic conception of Renaissance taste and aesthetics can scarcely
be exaggerated.
Are
sublime themes more characteristic of certain nations and peoples?
At first glance, they seem to be more typical of northern Europe,
where the greater extremes of climate facilitated their
appreciation. But what about Francisco Goya (1746-1828)? He was a major transitional
figure between Enlightenment and Romanticism and therefore perhaps
sui generis. Yet the Italian painter Salvator Rosa (1615-1673) was
often honored as the true pioneer of the sublime. Perhaps one could
say that the cultivation of the sublime in art began in southern
Europe, subsequently migrating to the north where it was most truly at home.
A somewhat similar trajectory characterized the picturesque, championed
towards the end of the eighteenth century by William Gilpin, Richard
Payne Knight, and Sir Uvedale Price.xxiii
Connoisseurs detected picturesque qualities in the atmospheric works of Claude Lorrain and other
landscape painters working in Italy. English collectors acquired
these works and then put them to practical effect in their great
landscape gardens. Then the concept helped once again to generate paintings,
sometimes landscapes but often not. The picturesque came gradually
to be identified with a certain freedom of brush stroke that produced
a deliberately imprecise, evocative effect. As noted above, the
picturesque did not so much displace the sublime as served as an
intermediary between the extremes of the sublime and the beautiful.
A subsidiary effect of the enthusiasm for the picturesque was the promotion of travel. A veritable mania set in for visiting picturesque sites, first in the British Isles (where North Wales was especially favored) and then in the wider world. New types of guide books appeared to satisfy the middle-class travelers' appetite for information. As the Murray and Baedeker guides were to demonstrate, one and the same book could serve to lead one to landscapes and to the works of art preserved in churches and museums. By the beginning of the twentieth century, the automobile was becoming common as a means of satisfying the tourists' demands to see new places and new works of art. The new fascination with the Romanesque depended in large measure on the newly won access (by car) to remote abbeys and churches.
A subsidiary effect of the enthusiasm for the picturesque was the promotion of travel. A veritable mania set in for visiting picturesque sites, first in the British Isles (where North Wales was especially favored) and then in the wider world. New types of guide books appeared to satisfy the middle-class travelers' appetite for information. As the Murray and Baedeker guides were to demonstrate, one and the same book could serve to lead one to landscapes and to the works of art preserved in churches and museums. By the beginning of the twentieth century, the automobile was becoming common as a means of satisfying the tourists' demands to see new places and new works of art. The new fascination with the Romanesque depended in large measure on the newly won access (by car) to remote abbeys and churches.
All
this traveling facilitated comparisons among the arts of different
countries. Yet the question of national character remained
problematic, and consensus remains elusive to this day.xxiv
The matter could perhaps be ignored altogether were it not that
writers on art themselves make such assumptions. Vasari, as has
been noted, believed that the Greek (i.e. Byzantine) and German
(i.e. Gothic) styles were not suitable to Italy. The young
Goethe, in turn, held that French and Italian art was not right for
Germany. More recently Sir Nikolaus Pevsner has sought to
define The
Englishness of English Art.xxv
These efforts to characterize art as a product of national spirit are
invariably flawed, but they tell us something about the historians
and their interaction with the public.
Wackenroder, Schlegel, and the Beginnings of Romantic Art Historiography.
Wackenroder, Schlegel, and the Beginnings of Romantic Art Historiography.
By
common consent the two countries in which romanticism, as sensibility
and aesthetic practice, first emerged to full maturity were England
and Germany. In England the romantic inclination had deep roots, and
accordingly was for a long time practiced directly, with little
theoretical reflection. Theory, when it came, was largely borrowed
from Germany, as the examples of Coleridge and Carlyle show. In
Germany, as the eighteenth century drew to a close, a general
intellectual ferment coupled with a need to escape the normative
bonds of French classicism created a powerful wave of theory
alongside creative works of romantic literature.
The
manifesto of the romantic approach to art in Germany was a slender
volume, the Herzensergiessungen
eines kunstliebenden Klosterbruders,
which appeared anonymously in Berlin in 1797.xxvi
The the book was written mainly by the short-lived Wilhelm Heinrich
Wackenroder (1773-1798), with additions by his friend Ludwig Tieck
(1773-1853), whose long and productive career was just beginning.
The friar who entertains these "Outpourings of the Heart" locates the source of all genuine are in religious sincerity. This
theme of a renewed subordination of art to religion was to become
common during the romantic period, but actual practice differed from
this ideal for, as M. E. Abrams has brilliantly shown for England,
the usual pattern was an aesthetism sheltering under the auspices of
nondemoninational pantheism.xxvii
For the
contemporary reader, the most striking contribution of Wackenroder's tract was
its aesthetic relativism. To be sure, the contrast of Gothic cathedrals and
Greek temples, each to be appreciated according to its own norms, was
by 1797 a familiar one, as was the contrast between northern and
Italian art. Much more novel is the injunction that non-European
culture deserves our respect. "Why should one condemn the Indians for
speaking Indian and not our language? In like fashion, Indian art
works will reflect the appearance of Indian peoples. So too we must
regard the artistic products of the Africans. Had you been born in
the African desert, then you would have preached to everyone that
glossy black skin, a flat round face, and short crinked hair were
essential constituents of the highest beauty." And when you saw
white men for the first time you would find their appearance
repellent and hateful.xxviii
Viewed objectively, it is not only that the arts of the Indians and the Africans simply are different from ours, it is understandable and right that they should be. These comparisons, while strikingly innovative for the period, may stem from the pre-Socratic relativist Xenophanes. who remarked that "[t]he Ethiopians say that their gods are snub-nosed and black, the Thracians that theirs have light blue eyes and red hair" (fragment 171).
Viewed objectively, it is not only that the arts of the Indians and the Africans simply are different from ours, it is understandable and right that they should be. These comparisons, while strikingly innovative for the period, may stem from the pre-Socratic relativist Xenophanes. who remarked that "[t]he Ethiopians say that their gods are snub-nosed and black, the Thracians that theirs have light blue eyes and red hair" (fragment 171).
It is not just that we can register aesthetic difference, but we can
school ourselves to savor the contrasts, for are not Germans capable of
crossing the Alps and appreciating Italian art? These few remarks
anticipate a whole program of world art history.
Another
Wackenroder contribution is the idea that art (alongside nature) is a
language, though one that is deeper than verbal language, for "words
cannot call down into our hearts the invisible spirit which reigns
above us." In order to bring us closer to this mysterious
spirit art uses the device of the symbol. Setting aside the
metaphysical element, Wackernagel foreshadows semiotics in viewing
visual expression and language as two parallel, though different
modes of human communication.
When all is said and done, though, the contribution of the Outpourings
to art history remained limited; it was more a manifesto than a model.
Wackernagel shows no real historical sense. In his eulogies of
Raphael, Dùrer, and other artists he relies on anecdotes.
Significantly, he quarried picturesque details from from Giorgio
Vasari's Lives,
but not the overarching historical schema. For Wackenroder art must
find its way back to the timeless truths that were lost at the time
of the Reformation. One group of artists listened to him and sought
to put his ideas into practice, the Nazarenes or Brothers of Saint
Luke, German artists who settled in an abandoned monastery in Rome in
1810.
It is
generally recognized that Friedrich Schlegel (1772-1829) is the
pivotal figure in the formulation of the theory of romanticism.xxix
Although his main concern was literature of the middle ages and the
early modern period, from the medieval epics to Shakespeare and
Calderón, he did make a concerted effort, in 1803-05, to understand
painting.
The son
of a protestant minister, Schlegel was reading Greek drama in the
original at the age of sixteen. His subsequent studies at the
University of Göttingen, where an atmosphere suffused by
Winckelmann's idealization of Greek art and literature prevailed,
confirmed--at least for a time--this inclination. Influenced by the
prevailing "Grecomania," Schlegel held that the works of
literature produced by the ancient Greeks were pure gifts of nature;
as such they were perfect in and of themselves.
During
the mid-nineties Schlegel turned to reading post-classical
literature. Retaining his former idea of the innate perfection of
Greek works, he concluded that medieval and Renaissance European
literature was indeed imperfect. His new ideas appeared in lapidary
form in the Fragments contributed in 1802 to the periodical Athenäum.
The gist of his idea, expressed in the famous Fragment 116, was that
our imperfection is also its glory: "modern" literature--or
romantische
Poesie,
as he termed it in his own jargon--is characterized by a progressive
striving for self realization, in which it always traveling but is
destined never to arrive. The concept of yearning (Sehnsucht)
is a core characteristic of the romantic sensibility.
For all
their perfection, Greek works have a major limitation. As one modern
interpreter has glossed his view, "[i]f the Greeks reached
finite perfection, the moderns (and hence, also, their poetry) are
imperfect at every stage, but they are infinitely perfectible. ...
Our defects themselves are our hopes, and there is no limit to our
prospects."xxx
In this way Schlegel gave a new interpretation to the contrast of
the ancients and moderns that had earlier raged in France and
England.
This
sense of progressive movement over time made the historical
positioning of particular works part of their essence. Hence,
Schlegel's ideas, which were eminently capable of adaptation to the
other arts, gave an impetus to historical study, especially of
medieval and Renaissance works.
Schlegel's
isolation of two contrasting governing principles, one for the
Greeks, the other for the later Europeans, is a two-source theory,
recalling the contrast advanced by Burke and perfected by Kant of the
beautiful and the sublime. It also shows close affinities with the
dramatist Friedrich von Schiller's dichotomy of the naive and
sentimental (1795-96), which may have directly influenced Schlegel's
formulation.
In
Paris in 1803-05 the German literary theorist turned his attention to
painting, using as his basis the tremendous collection of
masterpieces assembled in the Louvre as a result of the looting by
the French armies. Schlegel's observations took shape in a series of
reports published in his Frankfurt-based periodical Europa.xxxi
He shares Wackenroder's view that the essence of art resides in
fidelity to religious sentiment. Schlegel's earlier theme of
incompleteness as the essence of the post-classical found a new place
here. Gothic cathedrals, with their unfinished towers are the
clearest example, but even works that are formally complete belong
aesthetically to this realm of striving for ultimate realization. As
with literature, where no further works of the order of Shakespeare's
have appeared, he held that art had fallen from grace. While
literary excellence lasted into the seventeenth century, in art the
seeds of decay are already present in the later works of Raphael
(from about 1510 on). Schlegel's proclaimed enthusiasm for early
works is not new--it belongs to the general field of the enthusiasm
for the "primitives"--but he tried to characterize the
formal qualities of the works as having clear outlines and few
figures.
Schlegel
rejected the tendency, inculcated in the academies, to subordinate
painting to sculpture. Here he adhered to the idea, made familiar by
the Dutch writer Frans Hemsterhuis (1721-1790), that sculpture is the
characteristic vehicle of ancient art, painting that of the modern.
Our art being necessarily Christian, Schlegel believed, it must not
accede to a distortion caused by the intrusion of a principle that
was valid for the Greeks but not for us. His approach shows a new
nationalism, as seen in his praise of the early German school, and a
growing affinity for Roman Catholicism (to which he was to convert in
1808). Many of Schlegel's views about the attribution of works have
been overtaken by later scholarship, but he gave a vital impetus to
other more sustained efforts, notably those of Carl Friedrich von
Rumohr, whose achievement figures in the following chapter of this
book.
Wackenroder
and Schlegel agree, and many romantics shared their view, that the
presenting aspects of art--what the naive observer sees--are only a
part, and probably the lesser part. Genuine art works are symbolic
or "hieroglyphic."xxxii
While a complete account of these depths is probably not possibly
in words, one can still advance quite far. This hermeneutic quest
underlies the development of the nineteenth-century "science of
mythology," and ultimately the rise of iconography--beginning
with medieval iconography as initiated in France towards the middle
of the century--and its ambitious heir, iconology.
The
Attractions of the Exotic.
The
appreciation of foreign cultures served to augment the spread of
aesthetic relativism--but such knowledge was not easily attained. As has
been noted above, Wackenroder's remarks about Indian and African art
were very brief, and were not based on any actual contact with the
works. Even when works of other traditions were accessible, their
enjoyment had to overcome ingrained elements of chauvinism which
caricature foreign peoples. Thus until recently the French have
stereotyped the Germans as crude and aggressive, while the Germans
decried the French as unruly and decadent.
The
device of assuming the guise of a foreign observer criticizing one's
own culture is a sophisticated one. During the Middle Ages it
is impossible to find a European writer adopting an Islamic point of
view in order to look at his own culture ironically. The
voyages of discovery began to change this insularity, and already in
Montaigne one sees elements of cultural relativism based on an effort
to recreate in one's own mind the foreign point of view. In the
eighteenth century Montesquieu (Les
lettres persanes)
and José Cadalso (Cartas
marruecas)
exposed shortcomings of their own countries by couching their
critiques in the form of letters written by exotic visitors.
Perhaps
the first alien civilization to capture the consistent
admiration of Europeans was that of imperial China.xxxiii
Ironically, this enthusiasm for things Chinese was begun by
Jesuits who settled in the country in order to convert its population
to Catholicism. Later, Leibniz claimed that his invention of
the infinitesimal calculus was Chinese-inspired, and Voltaire regarded
Confucius as the ideal philosopher. Chinese porcelains were imported
because Europeans did not know how to produce this kind of
pottery—though finally in Dresden in the early eighteenth century
they succeeded in replicating the processes. But Europeans
showed little genuine appreciation of the Chinese aesthetic.
Certainly there were no attempts to write the history of Chinese art,
for Chinese objects, like Egyptian ones, were almost automatically
assumed to stem from an intensely conservative culture that had no
meaningful change and therefore no history. Judgments of
other cultures were much harsher, so that the English, even after
they had acquired most of India, continued to regard its sculptures
as monstrous idols.xxxiv
It was
not until the second half of the nineteenth century, beginning with
the interest in Japanese prints, that Europeans began actually to
attend closely to the qualities of "exotic" art objects that made
them distinctive, and to incorporate some of these qualities in their
own work.xxxv
In
architecture the babel of styles was noted even earlier.xxxvi
Ultimately this confusion of styles was to yield a solution in the
austere form of modern functionalist architecture, but while it
reigned attention was perforce directed at the nature and definition
of styles. The later nineteenth century saw the reexamination
of several styles that had been neglected or misunderstood, above all
the Baroque. These trends in varied architectural practice,
which put the variety of styles directly before the public, combined
with the earlier trend towards aesthetic pluralism, created an
understanding of the possibility of a much expanded history of art.
Some German scholars even sought to include non-European art within
its bounds, but the data available to them were insufficient.
Paradoxically, the sense of confusion and ambivalence in the practice
and contemplation of contemporary art produced a dividend in the
form of the enhanced appreciation of the art of the past. This
difference, however, probably contributed to the growing estrangement
of art history, addressing the past, and art criticism, focused
mainly on the present.
Politics
and Art.
During
the French Revolution the seating pattern of the National Assembly in
Paris (beginning in 1789) produced an enduring metaphor for
political orientations.xxxvii
The conservative parties sat on the right side of the chamber (as
viewed from the speaker's chair), the radical ones on the left.
While these terms fell into abeyance in France during the early
decades of the nineteenth century, they spread to Italy in the 1850s
and then to the rest of Europe. In this way right and left became an
easily comprehensible political shorthand.
Until
the retreat and then collapse of so-called "scientific
socialism" in the 1980s, many intellectuals gave an almost
automatic preference to the political left--at least in its moderate
versions. This allegiance is somewhat paradoxical in the light of
the history of hand symbolism: most traditional cultures favor the
left hand less than the right--it may even be taboo.xxxviii
In the Christian conception of the Last Judgment the damned appear
at the left hand of the Savior before being consigned to the eternal
flames. But perhaps these associations only heightened the sense of
transgression and defiance of traditional norms that many
revolutionaries felt in keeping with their wish to make an absolute
break with the past.
Another
new term in the political lexicon was "reactionary,"
referring to individuals who sought to stop, by all means at their
disposal, the growing forces of social change. But since progress
was inevitable--or so it was thought--the reactionaries could only
retard the timetable of progressive change. The opposite of
reactionary was the avant-garde, the vanguard of those who took a
position on the "cutting edge" of social change.
(Avant-garde and vanguard were originally military terms.)
It was
tempting, all too tempting, to apply these themes to the world of
art.xxxix
And in fact people began to speak of progressive and reactionary
artists. But what in fact was the art of the left? During the
French revolutionary period it was taken for granted that this was
neo-classicism, allied with the Revolution as the tireless activity
of Jacques-Louis David. In the middle of the nineteenth century
realism was considered the preeminently leftist style--a position
still held until recently in countries dominated by Marxist regimes.
This
exaltation of realism as the
revolutionary style, did not last in Western Europe. Although the
point was rarely explored in any detail, it became the conventional
wisdom to characterize changes in the program of "advanced"
art--including the sequence of impressionism, post-impressionism,
fauvism, cubism--as so many "revolutionary" advances.
After all, the political landscape of nineteenth-century France had
been characterized by a series of drastic shifts--in 1815, 1830,
1848, and 1871; does not art show also a series of sharp breaks? One
problem, which was usually neglected, was that some artists, such as
Cézanne and Degas, who were artistically "progressive"
were politically conservative. One way of overcoming this problem
was to say that such artists had "low consciousness"; they
themselves were unaware of the progressive character of their art,
and hence neglected to harmonize their overt political opinions with
the true nature of their creative accomplishment.
Another
term associated with both advanced art and politics was "experiment."
The French scientist Claude Bernard (1813-1878) popularized the idea
of the experimental method in medicine. Then came Emile Zola's
concept of the experimental novel. And art critics spoke of
innovative works as experiments.
Of
course this proliferating political discourse was not responsible for the idea
of artistic progress. As we have seen, Vasari and his followers had
held that art moves from primitive beginnings to a better state and
finally to a pinnacle of progress. But the new view colored the idea
of progress in art by linking it with political change. As a rule,
the importation of the contrast of left and right was the gambit of
critics applauding new works, rather than of art historians, who
preferred a more ivory-tower approach. Nonetheless, the politicized
view gradually seeped into the historiography of modern art, which
came to be viewed as an unceasing struggle against the forces of
reaction personified by the dodderers of the salon (the "artistes
pompiers"). Modern art was thought to be ruled by a relentless
dynamism, in which yesterday's revolutionaries (say, the
impressionists) turned old fogies, diehards blocking the advance of
youthful revolutionaries (the post-impressionists). Just as with the
cadres who dedicated themselves to political radicalism, adepts of
progressivism in art must be constantly on the qui
vive
so as to detect the most advanced trends and rally to them. In this
way artists and critics were seduced by the "more revolutionary
than thou" mentality.
But not
everyone wanted to be up to date. Sensitive souls sought to flee
from the rough and tumble of modernity and o find consolation in the Old
Masters. A flood of sentimental popular writings on Raphael,
Michelangelo, and Rembrandt reminded those in search of solace of art's past glories. A late product of this trend is
Bernard Berenson's (1865-1959) critical writings. An American who lived in Italy, Berenson sought an
ideal past in Renaissance art which, he held, supplies us with an unremitting
flow of "tactile values" as a consolation for the brutal
truths of the industrial present.xl
In keeping with the aspirations of his wealthy clients, Berenson
offered an escapist, elitist utopianism. Significantly, Berenson
first converted to Episcopalianism, and then Catholicism, before
returning to Judaism. Berenson and the members of his circle are
telling instances of the overlap between art as a surrogate for
religion and affirmation, however qualified, of religious belief
itself.
Neo-classicism
had posed the question of religion in an ambiguous form, since its
subject matter characteristically stemmed from pagan antiquity.
Finding allies in the Catholic revival, romanticism took a more
sympathetic view towards Christianity; it also turned to a more
generalized cult of nature. The romantic sense that the meaning of
life was not a matter of surface appearances helped to foster the
idea that in its highest achievements art itself was a form of
religious feeling. Symbolism was suffused with religious sentiment,
often of a deliberately vague sort. Then, in the late nineteenth
century, artists felt the attraction of occult "New Age"
religions such as Rosicrucianism and Theosophy. Needless to say, all
these "mystical" preoccupations were (and are) anathema to
those who advocated the role of art as an agent of social change.
Although
many art historians were personally conservative and therefore
resistant to the implications of the political interpretation of art,
this interpretation did help to direct attention to change. Whether
one agrees with the dichotomy or not, artists came increasingly to
define themselves as progressive or traditional, so that these
categories had psychological reality. Critics and art historians
have had to take these affinities into account. Recent discussions,
for example, have focused on the early anarchist views of Picasso
over against his allegiance, beginning in the 1940s, to the Communist
Party. Commitments of this kind cannot be simply walled off from the
creative life of the artist.
It
might be thought that the "nostalgic" exaltation of the art
of the past, which was generally hostile to advanced modern art,
would discourage historical study because it seemed to relegate art
to a timeless sphere of perfection. Yet this Golden Age approach did
reveal, perhaps unintentionally, how different the art of the past
was from the present and in this way called for a historical
interpretation.
Duality
in the Contemporary Arts: Neo-classicism and Romanticism.
Neo-classicism
was a broad movement that embraced literature and music, even
politics, as well as art.xli
On the one hand, it looked back to Greece and Rome; on the other, it
sought a new start, and in this sense could claim to possess
revolutionary content.
Winckelmann's
precepts were a major contributor to the formation of the
neo-classical style; this is the first instance in which the writings
of an art historian had a catalytic effect on the creation of a new
style, as distinct from consolidating our understanding of past and
present styles. Yet Winckelmann's passionate advocacy of his
aesthetic principles could not by itself have assured the success of
the new trend. Neo-classicism gained its adherents because
it linked up with the general movement of society. Because it
addressed larger concerns it became the dominant period style, which
it could not have done had it only been the manifestation of a single
sensibility.
Curiously,
in view of these strengths, the hegemony of the new trend was to be
shortlived. While neo-classicism was still at its height, in
the opening years of the nineteenth century, it was challenged by a
rival: romanticism.xlii
A protean tendency, romanticism resists any easy definition. But its
central goal seems to have been the exploration of our intuitive and
emotional dimensions, leading to a comprehension of the suprarational
or transrational elements of human experience as distinct from the
rational approach held to characterize classicism, considered too
narrow. With regard to sources of inspiration, romanticism favored
previously neglected or undervalued eras, such as the ancient Near
East, the Middle Ages, and Europe's prehistoric and early historic
past. In reaction to the universalism of the Enlightenment,
romanticism emphasized specificity--of the individual and of
particular objects and experiences. As the poet-artist William Blake
(1757-1827) remarked: "He who would do good to another must do
it in Minute Particulars. General good is the plea of the scoundrel,
the hypocrite, and flatterer, for Art and Science cannot exist but in
minutely organized Particulars." ("Jerusalem"). This
emphasis on specificity linked up with the sense of contemporary
German historians that the precise analysis of particular events and
mentalities was the great task facing their profession.
Some
artists displayed the influence of both trends, and are sometimes
termed romantic classicists.xliii
The Swiss-English painter Henry Fuseli (1742-1825), a disciple of
Winckelmann, is a telling example, for his works show not only an
attentive study of classical prototypes but a preoccupation with
uncanny medieval and folklore themes hitherto taboo, as seen in his
most famous work, The
Nightmare
(1781).xliv
Fuseli also created works based on Shakespeare's plays (interest in
the English bard was virtually a litmus test of rising romantic
taste) and on Germanic mythology.
This
"cohabitation" of two styles, the neo-classical and the
Romantic--in Western Europe implicitly posed the question of the
relationship of style to civilization. In earlier periods the
assumption of a single "correct" style had been taken for
granted, though there might be disagreement as to what it was.
In the seventeenth century Bellori thought the contemporary art of
the Carracci and Poussin admirable, that of Pietro da Cortona
execrable. The point was that for the discerning, contemporary art
furnishes reliable models of what is to be done. Now that
assumption, the call of the one, true style, was put into question.
It is no longer certain what the normative style is. Perhaps one
might even change one's style as one changes ones clothes, choosing
one style for one function and another for a different one.
Thus by the middle of the nineteenth century churches were
erected in the Gothic style, banks in the classic style, and prisons
and cemeteries (sometimes) in the Egyptian style.xlv
Other
things being equal, choice is usually accounted a human good. Yet
this style pluralism did not please everyone, for it seemed to
reflect a failure of nerve, a lack of the confidence and certainty
that had characterized earlier eras. Possibly the new pluralism was
even a symptom of pathology, a kind of social schizophrenia. So
the question continued to be asked: is there one style only that
is appropriate to a particular era? If so, what is it? And
finally, why should this commandment of stylistic monism be the case?
Conclusion.
The
effort to stem the "barbaric tide" by defending classic and
Renaissance standards to the death did not succeed. New fashions in
aesthetics and art--generally under the romantic aegis--assured that the world could not remain as it was. The
note of uncertainty sounded by the loss of religious faith and by
relativism was reinforced in an unsuspected way by the new
appreciation for non-European and medieval art. To anticipate the
theme of a subsequent chapter, the "taste for the primitives"
in the form of pre-Renaissance paintings of Italy and Flanders and
the revival of Gothic architecture opened the way to a vastly
enhanced appreciation first of medieval and then of all non-classical
art. Moreover, this understanding, in turn, fostered the
appreciation of neglected styles of more recent vintage, such as the
Baroque and Mannerism.
i
Arthur O. Lovejoy, in a challenging 1924 paper "The
Discrimination of Romanticisms" (reprinted in his Essays
in the History of Ideas,
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1948, pp. 228-53),
concluded that the definitions of the term are so varied and
contradictory as to render it useless. In due course, however, his
contentions were rebutted by René Wellek and others. Whatever one
concludes with respect to this controversy, a flood of
interpretive studies suggests that scholars continue
to find the concept useful. See for example, Stewart Curran, ed., The Cambridge Companion to British Romanticism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993; and Michael Ferber, ed., A Companion to European Romanticism, Oxford: Blackwell, 2005. There are also new approaches, e.g., Karl Kroeber, Ecological Literary Criticism: Romantic Imagining and the Biology of Mind,
New York: Columbia University Press, 1994; and Michael Löwy and Robert Sayre, Romanticism Against the Tide of Modernity, Durham: Duke University Press, 2001.
ii
A classic example is Thomas Love Peacock's 1820 essay "The Four
Ages of Poetry" (conveniently reprinted in Howard Mills, ed.,
Thomas Love Peacock, Memoirs,
Essays and Reviews,
London: Hart-Davis, 1970, pp. 117-32). The heroic ages of poetry,
Peacock maintains, lay in the past; in our own time science and
philosophy have marginalized the poetic enterprise. While this
judgment may seem quaint, in that it was rendered in the flood time
of British romantic literature, in the longer term it proved
prophetic. As the twentieth century draws to a close, poets
struggle--usually in vain--to achieve even a modicum of public
attention. On Peacock (1785-1866) and his relations with Shelley
and other contemporary writers, see Felix Felton, Thomas
Love Peacock,
London: Allen & Unwin, 1973.
iii
For survivals and transformations of Judaeo-Christian religious
themes in British romanticism, see Meyer Howard Abrams, Natural
Supernaturalism: Tradition and Revolution in Romantic Literature,
New York: Norton, 1971.
iv
The advocacy of art as an adjunct to the restoration and
consolidation of the Roman Catholic faith has been the particular
province of French writers, from François-Auguste-René de
Chateaubriand (1768-1848) to Jacques Maritain (1882-1973).
v
See e.g. Sir Nikolaus Pevsner, Pioneers
of Modern Design: From William Morris to Walter Gropius,
3d ed., London: Penguin, 1975.
vi
Richard Ettinghausen, "The Impact of Muslim Decorative Arts and
Painting on the Arts of Europe," in J. Schacht and C. E.
Bosworth, The
Legacy of Islam,
2nd ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974 pp. 292-320.
vii
George Kubler, Esthetic
Recognition of Ancient Amerindian Art,
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991.
ix
George S. Rousseau, ed., Organic
Form: The Life of an Idea,
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1972.
x
Allen G. Wood, "Je ne sais quoi," in Alex Preminger and T.
V. F. Brogan, eds, The
New Princeton Encyclopedia of Poetry and Poetics,
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993, p. 667.
xi
See the important article of Samuel Hold Monk, "A Grace Beyond
the Reach of Art," Journal
of the History of Ideas.
5 (1944), 131-50.
xiii
See, most recently, Jacqueline Lichtenstein, The
Eloquence of Color: Rhetoric and Painting in the French Classical
Age,
trans. Emily McVarish, Berkeley: University of California Press,
1993.
xiv
A useful overview is still provided by the older book of Kenneth
Clark, The
Gothic Revival: An Essay in the History of Taste,
3d. ed., London: John Murray, 1962.
xv
Herder has attracted much scholarly attention in recent
years--appropriately enough considering his portentous significance.
Among the most stimulating contributions is Isaiah Berlin, Vico
and Herder: Two Studies in the History of Ideas,
London: Hogarth Press, 1976, pp. 143-216.
xvi
On
the Sublime,
VII, 2; quoted after Monroe C. Beardsley, Aesthetics
from Classical Greece to the Present,
New York: Macmillan, 1966, p. 77.
xvii
The standard work is still Samuel H. Monk, The
Sublime: A Study of Critical Theories in Eighteenth-Century England,
New York: Modern Language Association, 1935. For a philosophical
analysis, see Walter J. Whipple, The
Beautiful, the Sublime and the Picturesque in Eighteenth-Century
British Aesthetic Theory,
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1957.
xviii
Cited after Moshe Barash, Modern
Theories of Art,1: From Winckelmann to Baudelaire,
New York: New York University Press, 1990, p. 78.
xix
See the exemplary edition prefaced and annotated by J. T. Bolton,
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958.
xx
Edmund
Burke's Aesthetic Ideology: Language, Gesture and Political Economy
in Revolution,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. Seeking to bridge the
distance between the Philosophical
Enquiry
and Burke's even more famous Reflections
on the Revolution in France
(1790), Furniss offers much useful comparative material and
bibliography. On occasion, however, his present-minded approach,
influenced by Jacques Derrida and other deconstructionists, borders
on anachronism.
xxi
Beardsley, Aesthetics,
pp. 218-19. See also Paul Crowther, The
Kantian Sublime: From Morality to Art,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.
xxii
For an attempt to trace collateral aspects of this Kantian heritage,
see Andrew Bowie, Aesthetics
and Subjectivity: From Kant to Nietzsche,
Manchester University Press, 1990.
xxiii
A large secondary literature addresses this topic. The classic
study is Christopher Hussey, The
Picturesque: Studies in a Point of View,
New York: Putnam, 1927. A recent monograph is Malcolm Andrews, The
Search for the Picturesque: Landscape, Aesthetics and Tourism in
Britain, 1760-1800,
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1989. For an exhaustive study
of the Italian background, see Philip Sohm, Pittoresco:
Marco Boschini, His Critics, and Their Critiques of Painterly
Brushwork in Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-Century Italy,
New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991. Several British and
American scholars seek to strike out in new directions in Stephen
Copley and Peter Garside, eds., The
Politics of the Picturesque,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
xxiv
For a collective study of national variations in romanticism, see
Roy Porter and Mikuláš Teich, eds., Romanticism
in National Context,
New York: Cambridge University Press, 1966.
xxv
New York: Praeger, 1956. As Pevsner acknowledges, he is indebted to
the Viennese art historian Dagobert Frey.
xxvi
See the English version by Edward Mornin, Ourpourings
of an Art-Loving Friar,
New York: Ungar, 1975. A useful review of Wackernagel scholarship
is Martin Bollacher, Wackenroder
und die Kunstauffassung der frühen Romantik,
Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1983.
xxviii
Mornin translation, p. 47.
xxix
A variety of recent views is represented in Helmut Schanze, ed.,
Friedrich
Schlegel und die Kunsttheorie seiner Zeit,
Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1985. For a more
general account, see Hans Eichner, Friedrich
Schlegel,
New York: Twayne, 1970.
xxx
Hans Eichner, "Germany / Romantisch--Romantik--Romantiker,"
in Eichner, ed., 'Romantic'
and Its Cognates: The European History of a Word,
Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1972, p. 105. See also his
article "Friedrich Schlegel's Theory of Romantic Poetry,"
PMLA,
71 (1956), 1018-41.
xxxi
These are conveniently reprinted in Hans Eichner and Norma Lelles,
eds., Gemälde
alter Meister,
Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1984. Excerpts in
English translation appear in Gert Schiff, ed., German
Essays on Art History,
New York: Continuum, 1988, pp. 59-72.
xxxii
For the history of this influential idea, see Liselotte Dieckmann,
Hieroglyphics:
The History of a Literary Symbol,
St. Louis: Washington University Press, 1970.
xxxiv
Partha Mitter, Much
Maligned Monsters: History of European Reactions to Indian Art,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977.
xxxv
The literature on this subject is very extensive; see Gabriel P.
Weisberg and Yvonne M. L. Weisberg, Japonisme:
An Annotated Bibliography,
New York: Garland, 1990.
xxxvi
J. Mordaunt Crook, The
Dilemma of Style: Architectural Ideas from the Picturesque to the
Post-Modern,
Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1987.
xxxvii
J. A. Laponce, Left
and Right: The Topography of Political Perceptions,
Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1981, pp. 47-68.
xxxviii
Anthropologists have given considerable attention to this question.
See Rodney Needham, ed., Right
and Left: Essays on Dual Symbolic Classification,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973. More general in import
is David Maybury-Lewis and Uri Almagor, eds., The
Attraction of Opposites: Thought and Society in the Dualistic Mode,
Ann Arbor: University of Michigan, 1989.
xxxix
For a judicious consideration of the problem, see Francis Haskell,
"Art and the Language of Politics," Journal
of European Studies,
4 (1974), 215-232.
xl
Ernest Samuels, Bernard
Berenson: The Making of a Legend,
2 vols. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979-87.
xli
For a clear, brief account (which perhaps overstates the link with
the Enlightenment), see Hugh Honour, Neo-classicism,
New York: Penguin, 1968. Some major aspects are acutely analyzed in
Robert Rosenblum, Transformations
in Late Eighteenth Century Art,
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1967.
xlii
The largely anecdotal account of Kenneth Clark, The
Romantic Rebellion: Romantic Versus Classical Art
(New York: Harper & Row, 1973) has been eclipsed by two
stimulating thematic analyses: Hugh Honour, Romanticism,
Harper & Row, 1979; and Jean Clay, Romanticism,
New York: Chartwell, 1981. See also The
Romantic Movement,
London: The Arts Council, 1959 (exhibition catalogue). In the
broader realm of theory, René Wellek's important theoretical essays
"The Concept of Romanticism in Literary History" and
"Romanticism Re-examined (in his Concepts
of Criticism,
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1963, pp. 128-228) seek to refute
Arthur O. Lovejoy's nominalistic contention that the idea of
romanticism is too sprawling and protean to admit of any precise
definition.
xliii
This point seems first to have been made by Walter Friedlaender,
David
to Delacroix,
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1952.
xlv
On the latter, see Richard C. Carrott, The
Egyptian Revival: Its Sources, Monuments, and Meaning. 1808-1858,
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978.
No comments:
Post a Comment